个人资料
正文

智障为自由民主政治招魂

(2022-11-18 11:53:19) 下一个

自由民主正在消亡吗?

Spencer Bokat-Lindell  

上周末,意大利选民将政权交给一个贝尼托·墨索里尼法西斯独裁政权嫡系政党领导的联盟,这是“二战”后欧洲极右势力最大的胜利之一。“今天对意大利来说是悲伤的一天,”意大利中左翼民主党领导人说道,在竞选期间,他视这场权力争夺为拯救国家民主的斗争

这种说辞对美国人来说耳熟能详,因为包括美国在内,全世界都出现了专家们所称的全球民主倒退浪潮。根据瑞典监测机构V-Dem——碰巧在瑞典,一个根植于新纳粹主义的极右翼政党也在两周前的选举中表现强势——在2021年,越来越多的民主国家正在退化,甚至滑向专制,程度比以往50年来更加严重。

 
如何解释专制政治的全球复兴,这又预示了民主怎样的未来?以下是关于此问题的一些观点。
 
自由民主正在后退
 
在过去几个世纪,民主的传播很少呈线性,而是随着专制势力的斗争起起落落。一些政治学家将民主制度的发展分为三阶段:第一波始于19世纪;第二波在“二战”后开始;第三波则始于上世纪70年代中期,在2012年到达顶峰时,全球共有创纪录的42个自由民主政体。根据V-Dem的数据,如今只有34个自由民主政体,与1995年时相等。(生活在自由民主国家的全球人口比例在过去十年也有所下降,从18%降至13%。)
 
正如时报的阿曼达·陶布解释的那样,近年的民主衰落——一些学者认为这构成“第三波专制化浪潮”,第一波始于上世纪20年代,第二波在上世纪60年代——主要并不是由政变或革命推动,而是通过合法当选官员的行为:“一旦掌权,不择手段的领导人有时会为自身利益操纵政治环境,使他们更可能在未来的竞争中获胜。通过赢得这些选举,他们获得了民主合法性的盖章认定——哪怕他们的行为最终破坏了民主规范。”
 
在欧洲,这种通过选举实现的“软独裁”最著名的践行者就是匈牙利总理欧尔班·维克托。在2010年被选上台以后,他通过侵蚀公民自由媒体自由打压司法重塑国家选举制度,建立了他所谓的“非自由民主体制”。在此过程中,他成了包括美国在内全世界极右翼分子的榜样。
 
虽然程度不同,几乎所有地方都可以看到自由民主规范和制度的衰落。
 
·在印度,2014年当选的总理莫迪推动了印度民族主义的急剧抬头——令国内穆斯林少数民族遭受暴力,且往往致命——并制造了极为压抑的言论环境
 
·在菲律宾,选民最近选出一位前独裁者之子来接替罗德里戈·杜特地,后者担任总统的六年里打击了新闻媒体,并发动了一场导致成千上万人被杀禁毒战争
 
·在萨尔瓦多,2019年当选的总统纳伊布·布克莱在国会部署军队向议员施压,无视最高法院要限制他军权的做法,在因帮派暴力而启动的紧急状态下,几乎没有正当程序就监禁了数以千计民众。
 
当然还有美国:政治学家警告称,共和党对自由民主规范的承诺已经减弱,如今其理念已经类似于欧尔班的威权主义政党,这种趋势在特朗普之前就已出现,但在他担任总统期间加速了。
 
不过,与其他许多倒退的民主国家的执政党不同,共和党在没有得到多数民众支持的情况下照样赢得了对政府的控制。正如时报的戴维·莱昂哈特最近所写,由于选区划分趋势和国会及选举人团制度偏向于小州的综合作用,如今美国政府的各个部门都倾向于一党(共和党)而非另一党(民主党),这种局面在美国历史大部分时间里没有出现过。
 
“我们无疑是世界上最反多数的民主国家,”哈佛大学政府学教授史蒂文·列维茨基对莱昂哈特表示
 
是什么驱使民主走向专制?
 
民主制度出现倒退的原因各不相同,但政治学家和各种人都提出了一些共同的主题。其一是对大多数人的民族认同感遭受威胁做出了强烈反应,不论这种感觉真实与否。
 
“首先,社会两极分化,通常是由于对社会变革、人口结构变化、种族民族或宗教少数群体政治权利加强、以及社会不信任加剧的强烈反应,”在时报广泛报道全球民主衰退问题的麦克斯·费舍尔最近解释道。“这导致了一种自下而上的渴望,希望秉持民粹主义的政界圈外人能够对抗所谓的内部威胁,这意味着压制社会上、政党中或是种族分歧里的另一方,主张一种赋予‘我方’特权的民主愿景,并粉碎阻止我方获得其主张的正当支配地位的民主制度或规范。”
 
阶级在其中发挥了怎样的作用?一些学者提出了民主倒退与“经济大衰退”——或者说全球自由市场资本主义本身的衰退——相关的理论。拿印度来说,蒂巴斯·罗伊·乔杜里上个月在时报上,“新自由主义政策加剧了不平等问题,国家在卫生和教育等问题上逃避基本责任。”他还表示:“这让无数民众过上了毫无尊严且无能为力的生活,只能在群体身份认同中寻求庇护,被承诺保护他们不受其他群体侵害的强人领袖所吸引,并容易沉迷于宗教仇恨这样的大规模精神鸦片,这种仇恨如今已将世俗的印度重新定义为一个印度教国家。”
 
纽约大学法学院的宪法学者理查德·皮尔兹持另一种实际利益角度的观点,他将非自由主义势力的崛起归因于政治权力在越来越多的政党之间的分散,认为这限制了民主政府有效运作的能力。“当民主政府似乎无法兑现承诺时,这种失败可能导致许多公民的疏远、听天由命、不信任和回避,”他去年在《纽约时报》上写道。“这还可能引发人们渴求威权领导人,这些人会承诺立即收拾肮脏政治。在更极端的情况下,它会导致人们质疑民主本身,并对反民主的政府制度持开放态度。”
 
民主的倒退能被制止吗?
 
历史表明,人类文明的轨迹并非必然倾向于自由民主。不过,它的专制倾向也是高度偶然性的。米格尔·安赫尔·拉拉·奥陶拉今年在《华盛顿邮报》上指出,自2000年以来,尽管民主倒退成为全球主要趋势,但也有九个国家在经历了一段威权主义时期后成功回归民主。
 
“这些国家向我们展示了民主的韧性,国家能够而且确实会回归民主,”他写道
奥陶拉所在的国际民主与选举援助协会提出了许多阻止和扭转民主倒退的想法,包括投资公民教育、改革竞选财务法,以及加强联合国、欧盟和非洲联盟等国际组织在维和行动方面的协调。还有一些专家则主张废除两党制,加强对科技巨头的监管,并对倒行逆施的政府施加经济惩罚
 
然而,也有人认为,技术官僚式的解决方案于事无补,无法解决问题。在2016年的一篇文章中,印度作家潘卡杰·米什拉认为,世界各地民主健康状况的恶化,是现代基于市场的自由主义意识形态自身的危机:一种对“技术、GDP以及19世纪赤裸裸的自我利益算计”的信仰,它既不能解释、也不能回答那些觉得自己被全球化资本主义造成的破坏和不平等甩在后面的人的愤怒
 
米什拉认为,为了开辟前进的道路,那些相信自由民主理想的人“首先需要一幅比经济人这个普遍形象更丰富、更多样化的人类经验和需求的图景”,他说。“否则,在我们对理性动机和结果的无谓迷恋中,我们可能会像那些无助的航海家一样——正如德·托克维尔所写,‘固执地盯着我们离开的海岸上依稀可见的废墟,即使水流正在前后拉扯中将我们带向深渊。’”
 
Is Liberal Democracy Dying?
 
Voters around the world are electing leaders with authoritarian tendencies.
 
 By Spencer Bokat-Lindell  staff editor.

This article is part of the Debatable newsletter. You can sign up here to receive it on Wednesdays.

Last weekend, voters in Italy handed the reins of government to a coalition led by a party directly descended from Benito Mussolini’s fascist dictatorship, delivering one of the biggest victories to the far right in Europe since World War II. “Today is a sad day for Italy,” said the leader of Italy’s center-left Democratic Party, who during the campaign had cast the contest as nothing less than a fight to save the country’s democracy.

If such language sounds familiar to American ears, it’s because countries around the world, including the United States, are confronting what experts say is a worldwide wave of democratic backsliding. According to data from V-Dem, a monitoring institute based in Sweden — where, as it happens, a far-right party with roots in neo-Nazism made a strong electoral showing two weeks ago — more democracies were deteriorating, and even slipping into autocracy, in 2021 than at any point in the past 50 years.

What explains the global resurgence of authoritarian politics, and what does it portend for the future of democracy? Here’s what people are saying.

Democracy’s spread over the past few centuries has rarely been linear, instead ebbing and flowing with the competing forces of autocracy. Some political scientists divide democracy’s progression into three waves: the first beginning in the 19th century; the second beginning in the aftermath of World War II; and the third beginning in the mid-1970s, which crested with 42 liberal democracies, a record high, in 2012. Today, only 34 liberal democracies exist, down to the same number as in 1995, according to V-Dem. (The share of the world population living in liberal democracies also fell in the last decade, to 13 percent from 18 percent.)

In Europe, the most prominent practitioner of this kind of “soft autocracy” by election is Prime Minister Viktor Orban of Hungary. After being voted into power in 2010, he has worked to build what he calls an “illiberal democracy” by eroding civil liberties and media freedomsubjugating the judiciary, and restructuring his country’s electoral system. In the process, he has become a model to the far right around the world, including in the United States.

To varying degrees, the decline of liberal democratic norms and institutions is visible in almost every region:

And then, of course, there is the United States: Political scientists have warned that, in a trend that predated Donald Trump but accelerated under his presidency, the Republican Party’s commitment to liberal democratic norms has diminished, its messaging now resembling that of authoritarian parties like Orban’s.

Unlike ruling parties in many other backsliding democracies, though, the Republican Party has been able to win control of government without commanding popular majorities. As The Times’s David Leonhardt wrote recently, because of a confluence of geographic sorting trends and the small-state bias of Congress and the Electoral College, every branch of American government now favors one party (Republican) over another (Democratic) in a way they did not for much of the country’s history.

“We are far and away the most countermajoritarian democracy in the world,” Steven Levitsky, a professor of government at Harvard, told Leonhardt.

No two democracies backslide for identical reasons, but political scientists and others have posited some common themes. One is backlash to threats, real or perceived, to the majority’s sense of national identity.

“First, society polarizes, often over a backlash to social change, to demographic change, to strengthening political power by racial, ethnic or religious minorities, and generally amid rising social distrust,” The Times’s Max Fisher, who has reported widely on global democratic decline, recently explained. “This leads to a bottom-up desire for populist outsiders who will promise to confront the supposed threat within, which means suppressing the other side of that social or partisan or racial divide, asserting a vision of democracy that grants special status for ‘my’ side, and smashing the democratic institutions or norms that prevent that side from asserting what is perceived to be its rightful dominance.”

How does class come into the picture? Some scholars have theorized a link between democratic backsliding and the Great Recession, if not global free-market capitalism itself. In India, for example, Debasish Roy Chowdhury argued last month in The Times that “neoliberal policies have compounded inequality, with the state retreating from fundamental responsibilities such as health and education.” He continued: “This breeds a life of indignity and powerlessness for millions who take refuge in group identity, gravitate toward strong leaders promising to defend them against other groups and easily become hooked on the mass opioid of religious hatred now being used to redefine secular India as a Hindu state.”

Taking another materialist view, Richard Pildes, a constitutional law scholar at New York University School of Law, attributes the rise of illiberal forces to the dispersal of political power among a growing number of political parties, which he argues limits the ability of democratic governments to function effectively. “When democratic governments seem incapable of delivering on their promises, this failure can lead to alienation, resignation, distrust and withdrawal among many citizens,” he wrote in The Times last year. “It can also trigger demands for authoritarian leaders who promise to cut through messy politics. At an even greater extreme, it can lead people to question democracy itself and become open to anti-democratic systems of government.”

History has shown that the arc of human civilization does not inevitably bend toward liberal democracy. But its tendency toward autocracy is also highly contingent. In The Washington Post, Miguel Angel Lara Otaola noted this year that since 2000, even as democratic backsliding became the predominant global trend, nine countries managed to transition back to democracy after a period of authoritarianism. “These countries show us that democracy is resilient and that countries can and do return to democracy,” he wrote.

The organization Otaola works for, the Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance, has proposed numerous ideas for halting and reversing democratic backsliding, including investing in civic education, reforming campaign finance laws, and strengthening coordination between international organizations with peacekeeping initiatives like the United Nations, the European Union and the African Union. Other experts have argued for abolishing two-party systems, more heavily regulating tech giants and imposing financial penalties on backsliding governments.

Yet there are also those who believe technocratic fixes are unequal to the problem. In a 2016 essay, the Indian writer Pankaj Mishra presented the declining health of democracy around the world as a crisis for the ideology of modern market-based liberalism itself: A “religion of technology and G.D.P. and the crude 19th-century calculus of self-interest,” it can neither account for nor provide an answer to the anger of those who feel left behind by the disruptions and inequalities wrought by globalized capitalism.

To chart a path forward, those who believe in the ideals of liberal democracy will “require, above all, a richer and more varied picture of human experience and needs than the prevailing image of Homo economicus,” Mishra argued. “Otherwise, in our sterile infatuation with rational motivations and outcomes, we risk resembling those helpless navigators who, De Tocqueville wrote, ‘stare obstinately at some ruins that can still be seen on the shore we have left, even as the current pulls us along and drags us backward toward the abyss.’”

Do you have a point of view we missed? Email us at debatable@nytimes.com. Please note your name, age and location in your response, which may be included in the next newsletter.

Can't We Come Up with Something Better Than Liberal Democracy?

The West’s favored form of self-government is looking creaky. A legal scholar and a philosopher propose some alternatives.

“Democracy is the worst form of government,” Churchill is said to have said, “except all those other forms that have been tried.” Actually, what he excepted was “all those other forms that have been tried from time to time,” with that last phrase implying that democracy is the root form, and the others mere occasional experiments. It was an odd notion, but was perhaps called for by the times in which he was speaking, the mid-nineteen-forties, when a war was won for democracy at a nearly unbearable cost. The art historian Kenneth Clark recalled appearing in those years on a popular BBC radio quiz program, “The Brains Trust,” and fumbling a question on the best form of government. The “right” answer, given by all the other panelists, was “democracy,” but this seemed to Clark “incredibly unhistorical”; he had, after all, studied the rise of Botticellian beauty in the Medici-mafia state of Florence, and of Watteau and rococo under the brute dynastic rule of France, and generally valued those despotic regimes where more great art and music got made than has ever been created under a bourgeois democracy. Wrong answer, nonetheless. He was never again trusted to be a Brain.

One doesn’t have to look far, even within the received canon of English literature, to find impatient dissent from the idea of the natural superiority of democratic government. Shakespeare found nothing good to be said for democracy or egalitarian impulses, trusting entirely to order and compassion to lubricate the joints of the state, even though he is the author, in “King Lear,” of the greatest of lines on the social perils of privilege: “Take physic, pomp, / Expose thyself to feel what wretches feel.” Dr. Johnson thought that democracy was obviously silly, and Dr. Johnson, let us remember, was a prescient, 1619 kind of guy, seeing the impending American Revolution as a slaveholders’-protection enterprise. (“How is it that we hear the loudest yelps for liberty among the drivers of negroes?”) It is not only possible to be an anti-liberal and not be reactionary but easily done.

These days, liberal, representative democracy—moribund in Russia, failing in Eastern Europe, sickened in Western Europe, and having come one marginally resolute Indiana politician away from failing here—seems in the gravest danger. Previously fringe views certainly find new forums, with monarchists speaking loudly, if a touch theatrically, but that is mostly strut and noise. What would a plausible alternative actually look like? “We’d all love to see the plan,” John Lennon sang sensibly about revolution.

And so, in search of a better blueprint for governance, we race back to Athens, the birthplace of the demos, to figure out what went wrong and how it might be set right. It’s a model that “Two Cheers for Politics” (Basic Books), by the political essayist and law professor Jedediah Purdy, keeps in sight, if in varying focus. Purdy sets out a program for fundamental change rooted in the virtues often thought to repose in the Athens of the fifth century B.C.E. Borrowing his title from E. M. Forster’s famous collection “Two Cheers for Democracy”—which included the unfortunate line about betraying one’s country before betraying one’s friends, a kind of motto on the shield of the Cambridge spies for Stalin—he has a nearly religious faith in the power of voting. Although his allusive manner makes it hard at times to distinguish the background of the argument from the point of the argument, what he has in mind would be distant from the liberal democracy we know.

At first, Purdy’s account seems a fluently erudite version of a familiar leftist critique of “procedural” liberalism. Liberals underestimate (or are fatally disingenuous about) the real role of money in bourgeois representative politics; politics in America, in particular, has been wholly “colonized” by capital. Our legislative assemblies are filled with rich people who mainly talk to other rich people. Reagan and Thatcher, or their financiers, brought about an era of plutocratic planetary rule, which hasn’t been reformed since. Blair and Clinton were mere handmaidens of the market, neoliberals making their peace with globalization and its inequality. Purdy treats the Occupy Wall Street movement with admiration, as a torch that burned too briefly. Obama was a failure who raised hopes and then defaulted on them; the first Sanders campaign was an authentic but also somehow dashed hope. Trump, significantly, is downgraded to a mere epiphenomenon, a symptom rather than a cause—a predictably decadent extension of neoliberal nihilism.

Yet Purdy does think that Trump’s campaign, like those of Obama and Sanders, signalled an appetite for democratic renewal, and a revival of “political energies that had receded far from the center of public life”:

In each case, some core of listeners felt “Yes! This is real. This is what it’s actually about.” The campaigns grew through the discovery that the listener was not alone: the political epiphany was shared. People felt freer to say things that they had kept to themselves or not quite known they believed and to take stances they had shied away from, assuming no one would join them.

The dead wasteland of a procedural liberalism managed by an élite, Purdy believes, has produced a crisis that only true politics—a popular belief in the possibilities of common purpose—can solve. For the worst form of capitalist depredation is exacted in the realm of the political imagination: “It has to do with whether we believe that we can decide the shape of our shared world.” He is angry at the élites who supervise the bureaucratic capitalist state on behalf of their overlords while keeping up an elaborate masquerade of equality of opportunity. Harvard gets hit particularly hard here: slots at Harvard College, he tells us, are bought and sold, while its Crimson meritocrats go on to staff “Democratic administrations,” the Times, and, well, The New Yorker. (Purdy was a chaired professor at Columbia Law School when he wrote the book, and, curiously, Columbia is left out of the complaint, presumably having arrived at a way of separating bold freethinkers deserving of their place from those dastardly meritocrats.)

Books of this kind, as all who write them know, invariably call up remote philosophical figures and have them hover about the text like floats at a Macy’s Thanksgiving Day parade, to be shown off or else deflated with a peashooter. So we get the usual run of Hobbes said this and then Locke said this and then Rousseau said the opposite and now here we are with Donald Trump having been elected President. A sensitive and subtle account of Adam Smith is followed by a less subtle, and less sympathetic, account of Friedrich Hayek, two centuries later. Walter Lippmann comes on, and Tocqueville, of course, is everywhere.

Yet a more radical thesis at last emerges, and with it the originality of Purdy’s position: he is not merely in favor of a renewed egalitarianism but disgusted with “representative” democracy in all its forms.

Rejecting the Founders’ faith in constitutional self-governance, he believes that a form of direct democracy must replace it—a “rough-hewn” kind, traditionally associated with what the ancient Athenians enjoyed, when any citizen might be called on to take immediate part in the decisions of the whole. There seemed then to be little space between the people and their decisions; if you wanted to convict Socrates of impiety—or finance the Parthenon with tribute from the Ionians—you cast your vote and the democratic deed was done. Purdy recognizes that the Athenian system was far from perfectly democratic; the voting population couldn’t all fit into the spaces for public assembly, and the polity did not include women or slaves. But, for the Athenians, it was effectively democratic: it functioned as a “synecdoche,” not as a metaphor, in a striking formulation of Josiah Ober’s. A small part of the citizenry stood for the whole.

The villain of the story, then, is not just the interposition of a “representative” class but the idea of representation itself, with its guaranteed declension into bureaucracy and élite rule. Nor is this an abstract or merely historical issue. Any New Yorker who has walked into his voting station to vote, only to confront a choice of unknown names listed for dimly understood offices—the deliverance of an inscrutable Democratic Party machine—can share the emotion that precedes the argument.

If Purdy does not have a very detailed plan, he has at least a plan for a plan. He wants to transform American life through mass participation in engaged and shared decision-making, of the sort presaged by Zuccotti Park. To get where we need to go, he argues forcefully for a reformed Supreme Court and a new Constitutional Convention every three decades, to rewrite the whole damn thing.

The familiar parts of Purdy’s polemic have familiar rejoinders. Occupy Wall Street was a marginal, not a mass, movement, never gaining popular support, and Sanders ran twice and lost twice. Purdy blames “market colonization” for the Supreme Court’s reactionary decision-making, but the Court’s most reactionary decisions have little to do with the desires of capitalism or, anyway, of capitalists: the Goldman Sachs crowd is fine with women’s autonomy, being significantly composed of liberal women, and would prefer fewer gun massacres. And though the struggle to maintain democratic institutions within a capitalist society has been intense, the struggle to maintain democratic institutions in anti-capitalist countries has been catastrophic. We do poorly, but the Chinese Communist Party does infinitely worse, even when it tilts toward some version of capitalism.

For that matter, would our democratic life really be improved by a new Constitutional Convention—to which Alex Jones’s followers, demanding to know where the U.F.O.s are being kept, are as likely to show up as Elizabeth Warren’s followers, demanding that corporations be made to pay their fair share of taxes? The U.S. Constitution, undemocratic though it is, is surely an additive to the problem, not the problem itself. Parliamentary systems, like Canada’s, have also been buffeted by populist and illiberal politics, while Brexit, a bit of rough-hewn majoritarian politics in a country without a written constitution, shows the dangers of relying on a one-night plebiscite.

Purdy’s basic political position seems to be that politics would be better if everyone shared his. Those of us who share his politics might agree, but perhaps with the proviso that the kind of sharing he is cheering for has more to do with the poetics of protest than with politics as generally understood. Politics, as he conceives it, is a way of getting all the people who agree with you to act in unison. This is a big part of democratic societies. Forming coalitions, assembling multitudes, encouraging action on urgent issues: these are all essential to a healthy country, even more than the business of filling in the circle next to a name you have just encountered for an office you know nothing about.

But the greatest service of politics isn’t to enable the mobilization of people who have the same views; it’s to enable people to live together when their views differ. Politics is a way of getting our ideas to brawl in place of our persons. Though democracy is practiced when people march on Washington and assemble in parks—when they feel that they have found a common voice—politics is practiced when the shouting turns to swapping. Politics was Disraeli getting one over on the nineteenth-century Liberal Party by leaping to electoral reform for the working classes, thereby trying to gain their confidence; politics was Mandela making a deal with de Klerk to respect the white minority in exchange for a peaceful transition to majority rule. Politics is Biden courting and coaxing Manchin (whose replacement would be incomparably farther to the right) to make a green deal so long as it was no longer colored green. The difficulty with the Athenian synecdoche is that getting the part to act as the whole presupposes an agreement among the whole. There is no such agreement. Trumpism and Obamaism are not two expressions of one will for collective action; they are radically incommensurable views about what’s needed.

Purdy’s faith in “collective rationality” as the spur to common action—his less mystical version of Rousseau’s general will—leaves him not entirely immune to what could be called the Munchkinland theory of politics. This is the belief that although the majority population of any place might be intimidated and silenced by an oppressive force—capitalism or special interests or the Church—they would, given the chance, sing ding-dong in unison and celebrate their liberation. They just need a house dropped on their witch.

The perennial temptation of leftist politics is to suppose that opposition to its policies among the rank and file must be rooted in plutocratic manipulation, and therefore curable by the reassertion of the popular will. The evidence suggests, alas, that very often what looks like plutocratic manipulation really is the popular will. Many Munchkins like the witch, or at least work for the witch out of dislike for some other ascendant group of Munchkins. (Readers of the later L. Frank Baum books will recall that Munchkin Country is full of diverse and sometimes discordant groupings.) The awkward truth is that Thatcher and Reagan were free to give the plutocrats what they wanted because they were giving the people what they wanted: in one case, release from what had come to seem a stifling, union-heavy statist system; in the other, a spirit of national, call it tribal, self-affirmation. One can deplore these positions, but to deny that they were popular is to pretend that a two-decade Tory reign, in many ways not yet completed, and a forty-nine-state sweep in 1984 were mass delusions. Although pro-witch Munchkins may be called collaborators after their liberation, they persist in their ways, and resent their liberators quite as much as they ever feared the witch. “Of course, I never liked all those scary messages she wrote in the sky with her broom,” they whisper among themselves. “But at least she got things done. Look at this place now. The bricks are all turning yellow.”

Purdy’s vision of democracy would, of course, omit the bugs in the Athenian model: the misogyny, the slavery, the silver mines. But what if the original sin of the democratic vision lies right there—what if, by the time we got to Athens, democratic practice was already fallen and hopelessly corrupted, with the slaves and the silver mines and the imperialism inherent to the Athenian model? This is the hair-raising thesis advanced by the illustrious Japanese philosopher Kōjin Karatani. In his book “Isonomia and the Origins of Philosophy,” Athenian democracy is exposed as a false idol. He does not see this from some Straussian point of view, in which Plato’s secret compact of liars is a better form of government than the rabble throwing stones at Socrates. On the contrary, he is a staunch egalitarian, who believes that democracy actually exemplifies the basic oppressive rhythm of “ruler and ruled.” His ideal is, instead, “isonomia,” the condition of a society in which equal speaks to equal as equal, with none ruled or ruling, and he believes that such an order existed around the Ionian Islands of the seventh and sixth centuries B.C.E., before the rise of Athens.

If Purdy is susceptible to the Munchkinland theory of social change, Karatani is tempted by what might be called the Atlantis theory of political history. Once upon a time, there was a great, good place where life was beautiful, thought was free, and everyone was treated fairly. This good place was destroyed by some kind of earthquake—perhaps visited from outside, perhaps produced by an internal shaking of its own plates—and vanished into the sea, though memories of it remain. The Atlantis in question may be Plato’s original idealized island, or it may be the pre-patriarchal society of Europe, or the annual meeting of Viking peasants in nightless Iceland. In every case, there was once a better place than this one, and our path to renewal lies in renewing its tenets.

Karatani’s Atlantean view is plausibly detailed. The settlement around the Ionian Islands in the centuries after Homer (but before the imperial ascent of Athens) was marked by an escape from clan society; the islands welcomed immigrants of all kinds. Free of caste connections and tribal ties, the Ionians were able to engineer a new kind of equality. They didn’t become hunter-gatherers, but they “recuperated nomadism by the practice of foreign trade and manufacturing.” Like fourteenth-century Venice or seventeenth-century Amsterdam, Ionia was a place where there wasn’t much land to till, let alone a landed aristocracy to own and exploit the terrain and its tillers, and so people had to earn a living making and trading things. As a result, they were open in ways that mainland Greece was not.

A key point, in Karatani’s account, is that Ionian trade wasn’t captured by a state monopoly but conducted through networks of makers and traders. The earnings of trade, under those conditions, were more evenly distributed, and the freedom of movement put a limit on abusive political arrangements. “The reason class divisions multiplied under the money economy in Athens was that from the outset political power was held by a land-owning nobility,” he writes. “That kind of inequality, and ruler-ruled relation, did not arise in Ionia. That is to say, isonomia obtained. If in a given polis such inequality and ruler-ruled relation did arise, people could simply move to another place.”

For Karatani, working in a Marxian tradition, ideas tend to mirror the economic exigencies of their contexts, and he thinks that in Ionia they did. The line of philosophers who came of age around the islands, usually called the pre-Socratics, were notably unconcerned with hierarchy or with religious mysticism. They imagined the universe as governed by material, transactional exchanges. Thales, who lived in the Ionian city of Miletus and thought that everything was made of water, was making an essentially empirical attempt to understand the world without recourse to fate or divine supervision. (So, for Karatani, was Heraclitus, a century later, who thought everything was made of fire.) Karatani insists that the pre-Socratic physics is inseparable from an Ionian political ideology. Ionian physics posited an equilibrium of forces, not a hierarchy of them with a mystical overseer. Anaximander, Thales’ protégé, “introduced the principle of justice (or dikē) as the law governing the natural world.” The play of forces in the physical world, fluid and forever in exchange, mimicked and governed the forces in the social world. Isonomia was at the root of it all.

Isonomia in Ionia—it has the rhythm of a song lyric. One feels again the shape of a familiar and accurate historical meme: trading and manufacturing centers tend to be markedly more egalitarian than landholding ones. Democratic practices of one kind or another—though limited and oligarchic in Venice, bloodied by sporadic religious warfare in Holland—usually take root in such places, only to be trampled as power consolidates and an élite takes hold.

Was Karatani’s Atlantis, that utopia of isonomia, actually anything like this? Early on, he cheerfully admits that “there are almost no historical or archaeological materials to give us an idea of what Ionian cities were really like.” But he suggests that we can argue by indirect evidence and by drawing “inferences in world history from cases that resemble Ionia.” These turn out to include medieval Iceland, also a refuge for exiles, with its famous Þingvellir, or meeting place, and pre-Revolutionary New England, settled by refugees as well, and marked by its isonomic townships and town meetings.

It is an odd way to argue history and has odd results. In Iceland, you can visit the Þingvellir, where the Viking democrats gathered—and the next thing you are shown is the drowning pool, where women were executed. The drowning pool came into use later, to be sure, but is part of a similar social inheritance. Rough justice, the sagas make plain, is as much an Icelandic tradition as shared goods are. And one has only to read Hawthorne to have a very different view of life in those New England townships, especially for people who did not quite fit the pattern.

Karatani’s historical approach—projecting his ideals upon an idealized past—has other confounding consequences. What are we to make, for instance, of his insistence that the poems of Homer, the bard of Ionia, are not aristocratic? In truth, the force of the occasional protests against aristocratic practices in Homer are moving because of their rarity, rather like the cries of the peasants in “King Lear.” “Blood will tell” is pretty much the motto on every inspired page. But Karatani needs Homer to be isonomic and will make him so. More practically, how did Ionians resolve the perpetual fact of political conflict? Perpetual secession seems to be the answer; when things get bad, simply go to another island. (The old liberal huff “I’m moving to Canada!” is more serious when “Canada” is just a rowboat ride away.) This is not always ridiculous advice—a series of successive secessions in New England is how we got Rhode Island—but it doesn’t seem like much of a plan for settled modern countries.

Greek islands before the rise of Athens, chilly and isolated medieval Iceland, the New England townships of the Colonial era: these sound like oddly sparse and remote spots to build a dream on. Perhaps all such dreams can be built only so. Reading Karatani’s account of ancient Ionia, one recalls the parallel dream of ancient Sparta, the militaristic state that so inspired authoritarians from Plato to Hitler. An isonomic Ionia is infinitely preferable to an authoritarian Sparta but seems of the same imaginative kind. We can’t build back better from a place that didn’t really exist. Certainly, from what little we do know, the Ionians seem not to have been egalitarian at all in the sense we mean and have gone far toward achieving—the aim of equality between the sexes, or among religious groups, or among ethnicities or sexualities. Yet the basic inquiry into the possibility of human relationships that Karatani undertakes is moving, even inspiring. Though he doesn’t cite them, his Ionians most resemble the classic anarchists, of the Mikhail Bakunin or Emma Goldman kind: repudiating all power relations, ruler to ruled, in a way that shames more timid liberal imaginations.

 
And if real-world isonomia seems likely to produce a group of refugees perpetually on the run as they flee one tyrant after another? This may not be a plausible basis for a polis, but it is a plausible description of a globalized intelligentsia. Here one comes to a really striking thing about books like Karatani’s. They reflect the existence of an absurd luxuriance of liberal and open institutions, which, for the moment at least, still engirdle the planet. In a translator’s note to “Isonomia,” Joseph Murphy tells us that “the text incorporates extensive quotation from Greek, German, Japanese, French and Chinese sources,” and he explains his elaborate methods of rendering all these quotations into one text. We take it for granted that a Japanese scholar will write about them all, in Japanese, and that his translations will be rectified with existing ones, and that Slavoj ?i?ek will be reached to blurb the work in his hideaway in Slovenia, and that Duke University—named for a toxic tobacco family—will label it Marxist theory, and that grumpy liberals will critique it. That this network exists, on a scale unknown to previous eras, is in itself astounding.

Liberal institutions—and nothing is more of a liberal institution, in its small way, than a university press—matter as much to our isonomic prospects as democratic practices do. Karl Popper’s point in his 1958 essay “Back to the Pre-Socratics” (although Karatani is critical of Popper, he echoes him here) is that what matters is not the content of the scientific theories of the Ionian philosophers (everything really isn’t made of water) but their “second order” traditions, their tolerance of dissent and appetite for argument. What matters is that, by arguing it out without feuds or heresy hunts, they eventually arrived at the theory of the atom, of which everything is made.

These institutions of open inquiry are foundational to the practice of democracy. As Amartya Sen argues, good primary schools contribute as much to democracy as strong political parties do, and, as Robert Putnam has shown many times, the presence of choral groups and cafés in an Italian town tells us more about its prospects than the wisdom of the laws in its statute book does. Such institutions involve gatherings of equals where authority matters less than argument, and where originality is prized—we want to hear from the guy who thinks everything is made of fire, since we have had enough of the one who thinks it’s all wet. Those gatherings aren’t as charged as the ones Purdy heralds in “Two Cheers for Politics,” but they matter in their very everydayness. Without the values, the practices are mere mummery, as in Russia; with the values, societies can remain open, even if the democratic practices are for a time limited—as in late-seventeenth-century France or even (look at that election list again) contemporary New York. Liberal institutions, what Frederick Law Olmsted imagined as commonplace civilization, are embodied in the circles of participation that silently surround both books. The effort to keep these institutions healthy, to keep the presses running and the coffee coming, is work we can do every day, and some small ground for hope.

Churchill was right: better than all the others that have been tried, from time to time, and here we are, in one of those times again. But is there ever any other kind of time? The nature of politics is to be permanently stressful. In Oz, once the house had dropped on the witch, Dorothy would discover that the Mayor of Munchkinland and the Leaders of the Lollipop Guild (not to mention the oppressed women of the Lullaby League) had violent differences in values and views, which the witch did not cause, though she might have exploited them. Politics, as opposed to pure power grabs, involves an acceptance of the truth that these conflicts can never be cured but only contained, and made as peaceable as humanly, or as Munchkinly, possible.

Politics is stress. The objective of practicing it should be to keep the stress from turning into cardiac arrest. Politics is, in this respect, a more desperate and tragic pursuit than those who pursue utopian ideals in its place may take it to be. The first cheer for politics is surely for getting people to act in unison; the second is for getting them to stop. 

 
Published in the print edition of the September 12, 2022, issue, with the headline “System Upgrade.”

 

dam Gopnik, a staff writer, has been contributing to The New Yorker since 1986. He is the author of, most recently, “A Thousand Small Sanities: The Moral Adventure of Liberalism.”
 

 

<<<<<<>>>>>>

“What Does the ‘Post-Liberal Right’ Actually Want?”

Produced by ‘The Ezra Klein Show’

“It begun to dawn on many conservatives that in spite of apparent electoral victories that have occurred regularly since the Reagan years, they have consistently lost, and lost overwhelmingly to progressive forces,” Patrick Deneen writes in a recent essay titled “Abandoning Defensive Crouch Conservatism.” He goes on to argue that conservatives need to reject liberal values like free speech, religious liberty and pluralism, abandon their defensive posturing and use the power of the state to actively fight back against what he calls “liberal totalitarianism.”

To progressive ears, these kinds of statements can be baffling; after all, Republicans currently control a majority of state legislatures, governorships and the Supreme Court, and they are poised to make gains in the midterm elections this fall. But even so, there’s a pervasive feeling among conservatives that progressives are using their unprecedented institutional power — in universities, in Hollywood, in the mainstream media, in the C-suites of tech companies — to wage war on traditional ways of life. And many of them have come to believe that the only viable response is to fight back against these advances at all costs. It’s impossible to understand the policies, leaders, rhetoric and tactics of the populist right without first trying to inhabit this worldview.

[You can listen to this episode of “The Ezra Klein Show” on AppleSpotifyGoogle or wherever you get your podcasts.]

That is why, for this second conversation in our series “The Rising Right,” I wanted to speak with Deneen. He is a professor of political science at the University of Notre Dame, and his 2018 book, “Why Liberalism Failed,” has become a touchstone within the conservative intelligentsia and was even fairly well received by liberals. But since then, Deneen’s writing has come to express something closer to total political war. And with three other professors, he recently started a Substack newsletter, “The Postliberal Order,” to build the kind of intellectual and political project needed to fight that war.

This is a conversation about what Deneen’s “postliberal” political project looks like — and the tensions and contradictions it reveals about the modern populist right. We discuss (and debate) Deneen’s view that conservatives keep losing, why he believes the left is hostile to the family, whether America needs stricter divorce laws, what the post-liberal right would actually do with power, the virtues and vices of policy analysis, whether post-liberals have built their core arguments around an invented straw man liberalism, Joe Biden’s agenda for families and much more.

You can listen to our whole conversation by following “The Ezra Klein Show” on AppleSpotifyGoogle or wherever you get your podcasts. View a list of book recommendations from our guests here.

(A full transcript of the episode is available here.)

“The Ezra Klein Show” is produced by Annie Galvin, Jeff Geld and Rogé Karma; fact-checking by Michelle Harris and Rollin Hu; original music by Isaac Jones and Jeff Geld; mixing by Jeff Geld; audience strategy by Shannon Busta. Our executive producer is Irene Noguchi. Special thanks to Kristin Lin and Kristina Samulewski.

“Is There Something Wrong With Democracy?” [The New York Times]

“Can’t We Come Up with Something Better Than Liberal Democracy?” [The New Yorker]

“What Does the ‘Post-Liberal Right’ Actually Want?” [The New York Times]

“The Republican Party Is Succeeding Because We Are Not a True Democracy” [The New York Times]

“Giorgia Meloni Is Extreme, but She’s No Tyrant” [The New York Times]

[ 打印 ]
阅读 ()评论 (0)
评论
目前还没有任何评论
登录后才可评论.